Generic selectors
Exact matches only
Search in title
Search in content
Post Type Selectors
Filter by Categories
Abstract
Abstracts
Addendum
Brief Communication
Case Report
Case Series
Commentary
Conference Abstract
Conference Editorial
Conference Proceedings
Current Issue
Editorial
Editorial Commentary
Erratum
General Medicine Original Article
General Medicine, Case Report
General Medicine, Review Article
IAPCONKochi 2019 Conference Proceedings
Letter to Editor
Letter to the Editor
Letters to Editor
Narrative Review
Oral Abstracts
Original Article
Palliative Medicine Commentary
Palliative Medicine, Letter to Editor
Palliative Medicine, Letter to the Editor
Palliative Medicine, Original Article
Palliative Medicine, Review Article
Personal Reflection
Perspective
Perspectives
Position Paper
Position Statement
Poster Abstracts
Practitioner Section
Report
REPUBLICATION: Special Article (Guidelines)
Retraction
Review Article
Reviewers 2023
Short Communication
Short Report
Special Editorial
Special Review
Systematic Review
Generic selectors
Exact matches only
Search in title
Search in content
Post Type Selectors
Filter by Categories
Abstract
Abstracts
Addendum
Brief Communication
Case Report
Case Series
Commentary
Conference Abstract
Conference Editorial
Conference Proceedings
Current Issue
Editorial
Editorial Commentary
Erratum
General Medicine Original Article
General Medicine, Case Report
General Medicine, Review Article
IAPCONKochi 2019 Conference Proceedings
Letter to Editor
Letter to the Editor
Letters to Editor
Narrative Review
Oral Abstracts
Original Article
Palliative Medicine Commentary
Palliative Medicine, Letter to Editor
Palliative Medicine, Letter to the Editor
Palliative Medicine, Original Article
Palliative Medicine, Review Article
Personal Reflection
Perspective
Perspectives
Position Paper
Position Statement
Poster Abstracts
Practitioner Section
Report
REPUBLICATION: Special Article (Guidelines)
Retraction
Review Article
Reviewers 2023
Short Communication
Short Report
Special Editorial
Special Review
Systematic Review
Generic selectors
Exact matches only
Search in title
Search in content
Post Type Selectors
Filter by Categories
Abstract
Abstracts
Addendum
Brief Communication
Case Report
Case Series
Commentary
Conference Abstract
Conference Editorial
Conference Proceedings
Current Issue
Editorial
Editorial Commentary
Erratum
General Medicine Original Article
General Medicine, Case Report
General Medicine, Review Article
IAPCONKochi 2019 Conference Proceedings
Letter to Editor
Letter to the Editor
Letters to Editor
Narrative Review
Oral Abstracts
Original Article
Palliative Medicine Commentary
Palliative Medicine, Letter to Editor
Palliative Medicine, Letter to the Editor
Palliative Medicine, Original Article
Palliative Medicine, Review Article
Personal Reflection
Perspective
Perspectives
Position Paper
Position Statement
Poster Abstracts
Practitioner Section
Report
REPUBLICATION: Special Article (Guidelines)
Retraction
Review Article
Reviewers 2023
Short Communication
Short Report
Special Editorial
Special Review
Systematic Review
View/Download PDF

Translate this page into:

Short Communication
27 (
3
); 448-451
doi:
10.25259/IJPC_426_20

Regulating Death: A Brief History of Medical Assistance in Dying

Department of Anesthesiology and Pain Medicine, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario, Canada
Corresponding author: Connor T. A. Brenna, Department of Anesthesiology and Pain Medicine, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario, Canada. connor.brenna@mail.utoronto.ca
Licence
This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-Non Commercial-Share Alike 4.0 License, which allows others to remix, tweak, and build upon the work non-commercially, as long as the author is credited and the new creations are licensed under the identical terms.

How to cite this article: Brenna CTA. Regulating death: A brief history of medical assistance in dying. Indian J Palliat Care 2021;27:448-51.

Abstract

Unique reports of suicide and euthanasia date back more than 2 millennia, reflecting evolving philosophies of death and dying as expressions of the mores dominating a given era. One longstanding theme in the history of decisions to die has been staunch opposition founded in religious claims that one’s body is a trust from the divine (and therefore not wholly in their ownership). The role of the physician has also been traditionally estranged from participation in such decisions, dating back to rudimentary conceptions of medical ethics in the Hippocratic notion primum non nocere (‘first, do no harm’). However, fundamental principles in the modern philosophy of medicine lend support to the idea that physicians can be justified in actions which cause some harm, in so far as they are acting to fulfil a greater ethical imperative. This brief historical review explores the inception of modern North American medical assistance in dying (MAiD) policy through a series of critical case studies in the unfolding of its practice. Medically assisted dying has presently been legalised in Canada and some United States jurisdictions, but with critical caveats surrounding circumstances of mature minors, advance directives and mental illness as participants’ sole underlying medical condition. While the modern regulations surrounding MAiD continue to take shape, the palliative care community is well-positioned to both guide and scrutinise the ethics of this practice.

Keywords

History
Medical assistance in dying
Philosophy of dying
Euthanasia
Suicide

In Athens, 399 BCE, the Greek philosopher Socrates – imprisoned and sentenced to death by hemlock on the charges of impiety and corrupting Athenian youth – famously raised a cup of the poison to his lips.[1] Descriptions of Socrates’ equanimity at the end of his life, and of his refusal to escape this fate when the opportunity presented itself, have invited the question of whether Socrates’ death was a case of euthanasia or suicide.[2] The distinction may seem peripheral, but we can imagine it likely to have been an important consideration for both Socrates and the jailer who provided his poison.

Medical assistance in dying (MAiD) is a modern name for an ancient idea, which has been a source of enduring contention for ethicists since the days of hemlock. The tools for suicide, euthanasia, and the expansive grey area between the two (ostensibly including MAiD) have evolved dramatically, but many fundamental questions have remained the same: who owns a life, and what are the ethical implications in advancing (or otherwise choosing not to delay) a death? The present article cannot, given its commitment to brevity, claim to offer a complete history of MAiD. Instead, it aims to introduce some of the answers to these questions through a historical lens by presenting a background for the philosophies of assisted dying, followed by several landmark cases in MAiD’s development. This abbreviated history of MAiD’s practice portrays how we can appreciate medical decisions regarding death and dying as expressions of the mores dominating any given era.

The Hippocratic Oath appears to contain a specific condemnation of MAiD: ‘(…) I will not give a drug that is deadly to anyone if asked (for it), nor will I suggest the way to such a counsel.’[3] Ancient Greek and Roman physicians did, nevertheless, sometimes offer such drugs to their patients for the purpose of euthanasia.[4] However, in the centuries to follow, many major religions opposed euthanasia for a variety of reasons. Among these were notions that life was a trust from God, and to shorten or prolong it would interfere with God’s plan; that artificially shortening life could preclude admission to the afterlife or reincarnation; and that suffering may have a divine purpose which ought to be accepted.[5] St. Thomas Aquinas condemned suicide on behalf of the Christian church in the 13th century, claiming that its completion interferes with the natural inclination of self-perpetuation, injures communities, and violates God’s authority.[6] Common Law similarly forbade suicide and physician-assisted suicide (PAS) in the British and French colonies that spread West to the Americas and, although Renaissance philosophers had begun to challenge ecclesiastical authority in Europe, several centuries would pass before the legalisation of human euthanasia developed widespread interest.[7]

The middle ages did supply a philosophy which would later find application in medical and ethical decision-making, coopted into arguments justifying PAS. For example, the Rule of Double Effect (ironically first appearing in Aquinas’s Summa Theologica) describes how – in situations where one cannot possibly avoid all harmful actions – an action that intends to prevent harm may be justified even if the outcome is harmful.[6,8] In medicine, this has been applied in scenarios where a physician might act to pharmacologically treat a patient’s suffering, knowing that the intervention may inadvertently hasten the end of life. The Danish philosopher Søren Kierkegaard developed a similar concept in 1843, describing granular conceptions of human ethics which are broadly applicable to the discussion of MAiD although not specifically applied to euthanasia in the canon. Kierkegaard’s ‘Tragic Hero’ character type would customarily abandon one ethical commitment in favour of another with a higher ethical imperative, therefore retaining social justification despite forgoing the former.[9] Applying this reasoning to MAiD: a tragic physician could forego the traditional ethical commitments to a patient – which include preserving life – in favour of imperatives to alleviate suffering and defend patient autonomy.

Neither formulation resolves the question of whether or not voluntary death could ever represent a higher ethical imperative, and several historical anecdotes poignantly illustrate uncertainty about this, even within the medical firmament. Samuel Williams petitioned in 1872 for euthanasia (using the term ‘mercy killing’) in medical cases of untreatable illness through analgesic medications, which were undergoing revolutionary developments at the time; a contemporaneous editorial in the Journal of the American Medical Association protested the suggestion that doctors ‘don the robes of an executioner.’[10,11]

In 1915, Dr. Harry Haiselden (Chicago, IL) recommended that the parents of a newborn with severe physical abnormalities not consent to a potentially life-saving surgery – presenting arguments tied to the eugenics movement – and, with the agreement of the parents, the baby died without treatment.[12,13] Public support for euthanasia waxed and waned in North America throughout the mid-20th century, increasing during the Great Depression (1930s) and decreasingly sharply in the immediate aftermath of World War II (1940s) when euthanasia raised fears of association with National Socialism.[14] Suicide was decriminalised in Canada in 1972, but the involvement of another party remained criminal.[15] Jack Kevorkian, known also as ‘Dr. Death,’ was one of the most prominent supporters and enactors of assisted suicide at this time in the United States: After reportedly assisting over 100 terminally ill patients to affect their own death, Kevorkian administered a lethal injection to a consenting patient unable – due to advanced amyotrophic lateral sclerosis (ALS) – to administer it to himself. The case was videotaped and broadcast by Kevorkian to advocate for voluntary euthanasia but, because his actions violated Michigan law, he was imprisoned for 8 years on the charge of second-degree homicide.[16] Amidst evolving controversy about euthanasia, a Canadian doctor writing under the pseudonym Dr. Gifford-Jones argued in 2013 that because Switzerland has long been recognised as provider of euthanasia for those who desire it (and meet Swiss regulatory standards), the only real barrier presented to North American patients by anti-euthanasia laws was the purchase of ‘a one-way ticket to Zurich.’[17,18]

In the early 1990s, a Canadian named Sue Rodriguez received a diagnosis of ALS, which would be fast progressing and fatal. Rodriguez became a national leader in the right-todie debate while seeking a physician to help her end her own life once she had lost the ability to do so herself. Rodriguez asked Canadian parliament, ‘If I cannot give consent to my own death, whose body is this? Who owns my life?’[19] The Supreme Court ruled against her 5–4.[20] The case came down to a conflict within Canada’s Charter of Rights and Freedoms: Section 7 describes individuals’ rights surrounding their own person, while Section 1 states that rights in other sections may be limited for the broader social good.[21] This is the Rule of Double Effect or Kierkegaard’s ‘Tragic Hero’ applied in opposition to assisted dying: foregoing individual liberty in favour of broader public safety or social good. Rodriguez took her own life in 1994, in British Columbia, with the help of an anonymous physician;[22] no charges were laid.

Current ethical arguments in favour of MAiD include respect for patient autonomy and evidence that assisted dying does not impact patient views of the doctor-patient relationship.[23] Conversely, arguments against MAiD include balancing patient autonomy with a fundamental respect for human dignity and a reverence for life, as well as concerns for the stability and motivations of an individual’s decision-making – with the legalisation of MAiD, many have concerns that money, guilt or coercion could play an inappropriate role in the decision to pursue assisted dying.[23] Recently, non-profit organisations such as Dying With Dignity have increased the public awareness of MAiD in North America through persistent advocacy campaigns. Although healthcare delivery is under provincial jurisdiction in Canada, the federal government is implicated in discussions of assisted suicide as murder is a federal offence. The Canadian province of Quebec declared itself in favour of MAiD in December 2015, anticipating the federal Bill C-14 (June 2016), which became the first Canadian legislation to legalise MAiD, albeit with several caveats.[24] Specifically, Bill C-14 does not allow MAiD in circumstances of mature minors, advance directives, or mental illness as the sole underlying medical condition – all three scenarios remain controversial issues. However, it does provision an impending 5-year review to revisit these circumstances with new evidence when it is available.[24]

Current MAiD legislation mixes a common language of its practice with certain geographical nuances, and international debate continues with a focus on universally defining the term and determining the exact circumstances under which it will and will not be permitted. These explorations attempt to address the ambiguity inherent in determining what conditions constitute a life so unbearable that the option of euthanasia can be ethically justified. They also raise the question of how much demand there would be for MAiD if there was greater accessibility of quality palliative care. While MAiD is legally recognised in Canada, its practice remains uncommon but not insignificant: as of June 2018, almost 4000 Canadians have chosen MAiD (accounting for <1% of deaths in Canada).[25] This has been partially attributed to a ‘Disability Paradox,’ wherein patients with severely limiting disease report a higher quality of life than others might expect them to have.[26] Nevertheless, to think critically about the ethics of MAiD while its regulations and limitations continue to take form, we must continue to engage with the core questions of who may decide which lives are and are not ‘worth living,’ and what rights and obligations should be recognised for both patients expressing an interest in MAiD and the physicians committed to caring for them.

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank Dr. Pier Bryden for her mentorship throughout the research process, as well as Drs. Harvey Schipper, Neil MacDonald, and Jacalyn Duffin for contributing their invaluable expertise on the history of MAiD to this project.

Disclosure

This work has not been previously published, although an earlier adaption of the same research is made privately available within the University of Toronto MD Program curriculum as an educational piece for the benefit of medical students.

Declaration of patient consent

Patient’s consent not required as there are no patients in this study.

Financial support and sponsorship

Nil.

Conflicts of interest

There are no conflicts of interest.

References

  1. . Plato's Phaedo Oxford, New York: Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press; .
    [Google Scholar]
  2. . Did Socrates commit suicide? Philosophy. 1978;53:106-8.
    [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  3. . The Hippocratic Oath and the Ethics of Medicine New York: Oxford Press; .
    [Google Scholar]
  4. , . Assisted suicide and euthanasia In: , , , eds. Holland-Frei Cancer Medicine (6th ed). Hamilton, ON: BC Decker; .
    [Google Scholar]
  5. . Religious perspectives on assisted suicide. J Criminal Law Criminol. 1998;88:1147.
    [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
  6. . Summa Theologica (10th ed). Barri-Ducis: Ex Typis Cœlestinorum; .
    [Google Scholar]
  7. . To Gently Leave This Life: The Right to Die Diana Baths, Vienna: Blue Danube Publishing; .
    [Google Scholar]
  8. , , . The rule of double effect--a critique of its role in end-of-life decision making. N Engl J Med. 1997;337:1768.
    [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  9. . Kierkegaard: Fear and Trembling Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; .
    [Google Scholar]
  10. , , . Palliative Care Nursing: Principles And Evidence For Practice: Principles and Evidence for Practice New York: McGraw-Hill Education; .
    [Google Scholar]
  11. . Physician-Assisted Suicide Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press; .
    [Google Scholar]
  12. . Disability and euthanasia: The case of Helen Keller and the Bollinger baby. Life Learnin. 2006;16:491-500.
    [Google Scholar]
  13. . The Black Stork: Eugenics and the Death of “Defective” Babies in American Medicine and Motion Pictures Since 1915 Oxford: Oxford University Press; .
    [Google Scholar]
  14. . A Concise History of Euthanasia: Life, Death, God, and Medicine Lanham, Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield; .
    [Google Scholar]
  15. Carter v. Canada, Attorney General 886 (BCSC 2012) . Available from: http://canlii.ca/t/frpws [Last accessed on 2021 Jul 01]
    [Google Scholar]
  16. . Kevorkian and Assisted Death in the United States. BMJ. 1999;7189:953-4.
    [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  17. , and . Assisted suicide and euthanasia in Switzerland: Allowing a role for non-physicians. BMJ. 2003;326:271-3.
    [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  18. We should not need a One-way Ticket. . Toronto SUN. Available from: https://torontosun.com/2013/05/01/we-should-not-need-a-one-way-ticket/wcm/e57f6e57-f49a-4a40-b757-519c55135539 [Last accessed on 2021 Jul 01]
    [Google Scholar]
  19. "Who Owns my Life?": Sue Rodriguez Changed how we think. . Windsor Star. Available from: https://windsorstar.com/life/who-owns-my-life-sue-rodriguez-changed-how-we-think [Last accessed on 2021 Jul 01]
    [Google Scholar]
  20. Rodriguez v. British Columbia (2018): Attorney General - SCC Cases (Lexum) Available from: https://scc-csc.lexum.com/scccsc/scc-csc/en/item/1054/index.do [Last accessed on 2021 Jul 01]
    [Google Scholar]
  21. Consolidated Federal Laws of Canada, Access to Information Act. . Available from: http://laws-lois.justice.gc.ca/eng/Const/page-15.html [Last accessed on 2021 Jul 01]
    [Google Scholar]
  22. Woman who Lost a Right-to-Die Case in Canada Commits Suicide. . The New York Times. Available from: https://www.nytimes.com/1994/02/15/world/woman-who-lost-a-right-to-die-case-in-canada-commits-suicide.html [Last accessed on 2021 Jul 01]
    [Google Scholar]
  23. , , . Assisted dying: The ongoing debate. Postgrad Med J. 2006;82:479-82.
    [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  24. Government Bill (House of Commons) C-14 (42-1) Parliament of Canada. . Available from: http://www.parl.ca/DocumentViewer/en/42-1/bill/C-14/royal-assent [Last accessed on 2021 Jul 01]
    [Google Scholar]
  25. Number of Canadians Choosing Medically Assisted Death Jumps 30%. . CBC News. CBC. Available from: https://www.cbc.ca/news/politics/maid-assisted-death-increase-1.4715944 [Last accessed on 2021 Jul 01]
    [Google Scholar]
  26. , . The disability paradox: High quality of life against all odds. Soc Sci Med. 1999;48:977-88.
    [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]

Fulltext Views
6,648

PDF downloads
736
View/Download PDF
Download Citations
BibTeX
RIS
Show Sections